When gay marriage was legalized in the U.S. in June 2015, many people cited the change as a sign that gays have achieved acceptance in mainstream society. In the months prior to Obergefell v. Hodges, the supreme court case that struck down all state bans on same-sex marriage, scholars engaged in a heated debate about whether or not same-sex marriage should be allowed. Critics of same-sex marriage include social conservatives as well as critical feminist and queer theorists.
The debate before same-sex marriage was legalized:

Social conservatives worried that same-sex marriage would undermine the stability of traditional nuclear families and the sanctity of marriage. These scholars see heterosexual marriage and the heterosexual nuclear family as the foundation of society – resting on a gendered division of labor, a confining of women to the private, familial sphere of society, and monogamous partnership. Their logic followed that this method of social organization was the bedrock for raising healthy, moral children, and a healthy, moral society (Dobson 2004; Elshtain 1991; Lutzer 2004; Josephson 2005). Social conservatives also feared the sexual promiscuity attached to same-sex couples would erode the institution of marriage by exposing children of same-sex couples to non-normative sexual practices such as polyamory (Dobson 2004). Marriage as an institution connects sex with reproduction, a Christian value — and thus, social conservative scholars feared allowing homosexuals to access the institution would destabilize this connection by acknowledging nonprocreative sex as a legitimate practice (Gallagher 2003; Baskerville 2006; Lutzer 2004).
Other critics of same-sex marriage, critical feminists and queer theorists, were concerned that same-sex marriage would reinforce patriarchal and heteronormative relations. Feminists who adopt a critical perspective of the struggle for marriage equality contend that it will produce institutionalized gender-role differentiated marriages (Lehr 1999; Robson 1992; Walters 2001) and a new type of same-sex nuclear family based in heterosexual values of monogamy, parenthood, and the concept of partners as property (Auchmuty 2004; Baird and Rosenbaum 1997; Butler 1996; Ettelbrick 1997; Lehr 1999; Polikoff 1993; Walters 2001). For these reasons, many queer theorists fundamentally reject same-sex marriage because they believe engaging in the institution assimilates queers to heteronormativity through forcing them to adhere to the norms associated with traditional heterosexual marriage. Duggan (2002: 176) denotes this “homonormativity.” Valverde (2006:156) finds in same-sex marriage the birth of a new norm for assimilated homosexuals: a “respectable same-sex couple” — a gentrified downtown home, nuclear family, joint bank accounts, and good style.
Some feminists even say same-sex marriage is a “sell out” (Baird and Rosenbaum 1997: 11); incapable of rehabilitation (Saalfield 1993), and unworthy of the queer struggle (Ettelbrick 1997). These theorists question the queer community’s focus on marriage equality, and instead believe queers should focus their activism toward more pressing issues such as racial and classed inequalities in larger society and within the queer community.
Proponents of same-sex marriage argue marriage confers rights that same-sex couples are entitled to: inheritance, health benefits, taxation, parenting, and childcare (Eskridge and Spedale 2006; Sullivan 1996; Walters 2001). They argue that legalized same-sex partnerships lack the social and symbolic legitimation of marriage, leading to an almost “second-class citizenship” for lesbian and gay couples. Some queer theorists find positivity in the same things critical queers are concerned with: these theorists contend marriage will provide stability for same-sex partnerships by reigning in the libido and promoting monogamy (Hausknecht 2003; Josephson 2005; Raunch 1997; Rotello 1997; Sullivan 1996). While queer theorists critical of same-sex marriage find the promotion of monogamy to be a normative heterosexual value, other queer theorists think this could be good for promoting stable couples within the queer community.
What are the results?
Since same-sex marriage has been legalized, scholars have continued to debate how queers’ acceptance into the institution will affect society, queer community, and the institution of marriage itself. Does the legalization of same-sex marriage lead to “homonormativity” – queers assimilating into heterosexual society through adopting their norms of behavior?

Some scholars predicted gays and lesbians would transform the institution rather than the institution transforming them (Green 2010; Taylor and Rupp 2014; Graff 1997). Sociologist Adam Green conducted a study of same-sex spouses to explore these claims. He found that his interviewees’ marital status allowed them and their relationships societal recognition, which facilitated more access to support from not only of family and friends, but also co-workers and employers. The same-sex spouses in his study felt their marital status positively influenced their social capital — the social resources they have access to that promote financial and emotional well-being.
Green also found that same-sex marriages resist assimilating to the norms typical of heterosexual marriage, and in effect, they “queer” marriage as an institution. For example, participants engaged in non-monogamous norms and practices, negotiated the domestic division of labor and authority in a way that resists traditional gendered roles, and do not necessarily conform to the nuclear familial structure. Other scholars’ research underscores these points: a vast majority of same-sex couples articulate highly egalitarian domestic division of labor organized by individual interests and desires, rather than predetermined role-differentiated tasks (Dunne and Sullivan 2004; Blumstein and Schwarz 1983; Dunne 1997; Patterson 1995), and non-normative sexual desires and practices are still a central value of queer partnership (Albertson 2014).
Given the debate and these results, I propose we adopt a different perspective on the subject of same-sex marriage. Instead of perceiving of this change as a loss for the queer community, or as a “sell out,” trading rights for assimilation into “acceptable” behavior, we should see queers as the powerful political forces they are. Let’s recognize queers’ access to marriage as an institution constitutes a “queering” of one of the most traditional institutions in our society. Queers have infiltrated an institution that has historically been used to enforce gender roles, oppression of women, and normative sexuality. Some queers may continue to advocate for the abolition of marriage as an institution due to its harmful historical effects – however, I see this as an opportunity for us. We queers have the chance to erode the institution of marriage and separate its symbolism as the ultimate signifier of love from the heterosexual oppressive norms it promotes and enforces. Come one, come all, down to the court house — it’s time we queers destabilize some heterosexual structures!
Works Cited
Albertson, Cory. “Looking—Who Are We Now?” Contexts, vol. 13, no. 4, 2014, pp. 54–56.
Baird, R.M. and S.E. Rosenbaum. 1997. Same-Sex Marriage: The Moral and Legal Debate. Amherst: Prometheus.
Auchmuty, Rosemary. 2004. Same-sex marriage revived: Feminist critique and legal strategy. Feminism & Psychology 14(1):101–126.
Baird, R.M. and S.E. Rosenbaum. 1997. Same-Sex Marriage: The Moral and Legal Debate. Amherst: Prometheus.
Baskerville, Stephen. 2006. The real danger of same-sex marriage. The Family in America. Online Edition. 20, 5, 6.
Bevacqua, Maria. 2004. Feminist theory and the question of lesbian and gay marriage. Feminism & Psychology 14(1):36–40.
Blumstein, Phillip and Pepper Schwartz. 1983. American Couples: Money, Work and Sex. New York: William Morrow.
Butler, Judith. 2002. Is kinship always already heterosexual? Difference 13(1):14–44.
Dobson, James. 2004. Marriage Under Fire: Why We Must Win This Battle. Oregon: Multnomah.
Duggan, Lisa. 2002. The new homonormativity: The sexual politics of neoliberalism. Pp. 175–194 in Russ Castronovo and Dana Nelson, eds., Materializing Democracy: Toward a Revitalized Cultural Politics. Durham: Duke University Press.
Dunne, Gillian A. 1997. Lesbian Lifestyles: Women’s Work and the Politics of Sexuality. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Elshtain, Jean Bethke. 1991. Against marriage – II. Accepting limits. Commonweal 1(118):685-686.
Eskridge, William. 2002. Gaylaw: Challenging the Apartheid of the Closet. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ettelbrick, P. 1997. Since when is marriage a path to liberation? Pp. 118–124 in Andrew Sullivan, ed., Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con. New York: Vintage.
Gallagher, Maggie. 2003. The divorce thing: A diversion in the marriage debate. The National Review Online. August 13.
Graff, E.J. 1997. Retying the knot. Pp. 134–138 in Andrew Sullivan, ed., SameSex Marriage: Pro and Con. New York: Vintage.
Gross, Neil. 2005. The detraditionalization of intimacy reconsidered. Sociological Theory 23(3):286–311.
Hausknecht, Murray. 2003. Gay marriage and the domestication of sex. Dissent Fall: 8–10.
Herdt, Gilbert. 1992. Coming out as a rite of passage: A Chicago study. Pp 29–67 in Gilbert Herdt, ed., Gay Culture in America. Boston: Beacon Press.
Josephson, Jyl. 2005. Citizenship, same-sex marriage, and feminist critiques of marriage. Perspectives on Politics 3(2):269–284
Kane, Emily W. 2006. “No way my boys are going to be like that!”: Parents’ response to gender nonconformity. Gender & Society 20:149-7
Lehr, Valerie. 1999. Queer Family Values: Debunking the Myth of the Nuclear Family. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Lutzer, Erwin. 2004. The Truth About Same-Sex Marriage. Chicago: Moody Publishers.
Taylor, Verta, and Leila j. Rupp. “Are We Still Queer Even Though We’re Married?” Contexts, vol. 13, no. 2, 2014, pp. 84–87. JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/43872921. Accessed 5 Dec. 2020.
Patterson, Charlotte, J. 1995. Families of the lesbian baby-boom: Parents’ division of labor and children’s adjustment. Developmental Psychology 31:115–123.
Polikoff, Nancy. 1993. We will get what we ask for: Why legalizing gay and lesbian marriage will not dismantle the legal structure of gender in every marriage. VA Law Review 79:1535
Raunch, J. 1997. For better or worse? Pp. 169–181 in Andrew Sullivan, ed., Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con. New York: Vintage
Robson, Ruthann. 1992. Lesbian (out)law: Survival Under the Rule of Law. Ithaca, NY: Firebrand Books.
Rotello, Gabriel. 1997. Sexual Ecology: AIDS and the Destiny of Gay Men. New York: Dutton.
Saalfield, C. 1993. Lesbian marriage…(k)not! Pp. 187–195 in Arlene Stein, ed., Sisters, Sexperts, Queers: Beyond the Lesbian Nation. New York: Panguin.
Sullivan, Andrew. 1996. Here comes the groom: A (conservative) case for gay marriage. Pp. 252– 258 in B. Bawer, ed., Beyond Queer. New York: Free Press.
Valverde, Mariana. 2006. A new entity in the history of sexuality: The respectable same-sex couple. Feminist Studies 32(1):155–163.
Walters, S.D. 2001. Take my domestic partner, please: Gays and marriage in the era of the visible. Pp. 338–357 in Mary Bernstein and R. Reinmann, eds., Queer Families, Queer Politics: Challenging Culture and the State. New York: Columbia University Press.